Etikk i praksis. Nordic Journal of Applied Ethics (2018), 13(1),  5–20
http://dx.doi.org/10.5324/eip.v13i1.2726

Lessons of Reproductive Ethics for Principlism


Morten Dige

Department of Philosophy and History of Ideas, Aarhus University, filmd@cas.au.dk

This article brings together two debates in bioethics more substantively than has been the case until now. One is the methodological debate over "principlism," i.e., the theoretical framework for analyzing and solving (bio)ethical problems proposed by Beauchamp and Childress in Principles of Biomedical Ethics (PBE). The other is the normative debate about reproductive ethics, i.e., procreative rights and obligations in a time of pervasive opportunities for making detailed choices about the properties and capacities of future people. The obvious point of bringing the debates together is to show how they can illuminate each other in fruitful ways consistent with the method of reflective equilibrium endorsed in PBE. Furthermore, discussions of reproductive ethics is almost absent in PBE, making it an interesting "test case" on how principlist theory can have an impact on and be affected by confrontations with new practices and considerations in biomedicine. Reproductive ethics is especially interesting due to the so-called non-identity considerations, which pose a challenge to common morality views on harm to and respect for persons. My focus is mainly on some methodological points about the import of concrete normative discussions for formulating basic normative principles. However, I unfold a number of substantial points in order to demonstrate this. It is my impression that most writers on principlism underestimate the effect of engaging with concrete problems. Specifically, I conclude that reflecting on procreative obligations provides strong reasons for specifying the basic principles in ways that uncover new dimensions of them and not just new applications.

 

Keywords: principlism, reproductive ethics, non-identity problem, nonmaleficence, respect for persons

 


Principles and principlism

Principles of Biomedical Ethics by Tom Beauchamp & James Childress (PBE in the following) is undoubtedly the most influential work in bioethics, and arguably in practical ethics more broadly. It has undergone quite substantial revisions from the first edition in 1979 to the seventh in 2013. The set of basic principles, however, has remained stable through all editions: 
(1) respect for autonomy (a norm of respecting and supporting autonomous decisions), (2) nonmaleficence (a norm of avoiding the causation of harm), (3) beneficence (a group of norms pertaining to relieving, lessening, or preventing harm and providing benefits and balancing benefits against risks and costs), and (4) justice (a group of norms for fairly distributing benefits, risks, and costs) (Beauchamp & Childress 2013: 13).
The PBE approach has been dominant to the extent that it is often equated with “principlism” or the principle-based approach. There are competing accounts, however, notably the set of principles developed by Bernard Gert and his co-authors (Clouser, Culver & Gert 2006) and the (so-called) “European” principles developed by Rendtorff and Kemp (Rendtorff & Kemp 2000). Thus, on the face of it, the four principles just listed are not necessarily definitive, and it is in many ways both illuminating and indeed required by the method of reflective equilibrium to challenge the PBE set by comparing it with alternative accounts. For purposes of the discussion to come, I will restrict myself to a brief comparison with and discussion of a very similar but nonetheless importantly different set of principles, namely the principles stated in The Belmont Report (BR in the following) on the protection of human research subjects from 1978. The report was a reaction to a strongly felt need for protection of human research subjects made most vivid by the scandal surrounding the Tuskegee Study of Untreated Syphilis in the Negro Male. The study involved hundreds of impoverished black Alabama citizens suffering from syphilis who were deliberately not treated and not informed about their condition in order to study the "natural" progression of the disease. When the scandal finally broke in 1972 after forty years, numerous men had died of syphilis, 40 wives had contracted the disease, and 19 children had been born with congenital syphilis (Wikipedia).

The report established three ethical principles for the protection of human research subjects: (1) respect for persons, (2) beneficence, and (3) justice. Unlike the PBE set, there is no independent principle of nonmaleficence, and respect for autonomy is replaced by a (seemingly broader) principle of respect for persons.

Tom Beauchamp served as a member of the professional staff of the committee behind the report and it is tempting to see it as a “prequel” to PBE, in which the more developed set of principles is stated. The truth is, however, that BR and PBE were worked out simultaneously and just had different publication speeds (Beauchamp 2010). A better explanation of the difference is that Beauchamp entered the committee at a stage where decisions about the basic principles had already been made. Thus, it is fair to see them as an alternative, and not just a less developed, set. I think the establishment of nonmaleficence as a freestanding principle is a change for the better even though the dividing line between beneficence and nonmaleficence is open for debate. The reduction of the principle of respect for persons to respect for autonomy is not as substantial as it may look but nonetheless a suitable opportunity for critical reflections. In the following, I present some of the reasons for these two points of critique. Later, I will show how they illuminate some of the important controversies in reproductive ethics.
 
The division between beneficence and nonmaleficence
Reasons of nonmaleficence are not absent in BR but they are subsumed under the principle of beneficence. The report states the following:
Two general rules have been formulated as complementary expressions of beneficent actions in this sense: (1) do not harm and (2) maximize possible benefits and minimize possible harms. (National Commission 1978, p. 6, emphasis mine)
Even so, the absence of the principle of nonmaleficence as a freestanding principle is striking. In the Tuskegee study, it seems natural to say that the primary wrong, morally speaking, was that people were harmed by the deliberate deception about their condition. It was not just that it involved, first, a lack of informed consent (disrespect for persons), second, a pernicious racial or racist bias (injustice), and third, a failure to minimize possible harms and provide beneficent treatment – bad enough as that is. Several participants were actively prevented from accessing syphilis treatment programs and thus quite directly harmed (Jones 1981: 177).

All this is of course to some extent a question of how to divide the issues between beneficence and nonmaleficence. PBE list prevention and removal of harm under the principle of beneficence. Only the direct infliction of evil or harm falls under the principle of nonmaleficence. This obviously has a certain support in the common morality. Most people believe that a fundamental asymmetry exists between these two types of moral demands. As some of the famous “sacrificing one to save others” examples show, it is not easy to reduce one type to the other.1 There are several possible reasons for this. I would like (briefly) to point out two.

First, as Beauchamp and Childress also point out, rules of nonmaleficence are negative and impartial, i.e., we can fulfill them simply by not committing certain acts and they apply equally no matter our relation to the potential victim. Rules of beneficence, on the contrary require positive actions and can often (and sometimes should) be applied partially depending on our relationships with the potential beneficiary.

Second, in cases of sacrificing one to save others, even if we produce some good by inflicting evil or harm, we still need to be "guided by evil" (see Nagel 1986: 181f) - we need to direct our actions in ways that we know will harm another person. Regardless of whether we think that such an action can sometimes (in exceptional circumstances) be morally justified, it seems clear that it is categorically different from cases in which we neglectfully fail to prevent or remove evil or harm. Bad as such omissions often are, they normally do not involve this kind of schizophrenic intention.

PBE’s division between nonmaleficence and beneficence is thus not without foundation. Even so, it is not entirely obvious that it gives a perfect reflection of the common morality. At least in some contexts it seems to me clear that the most important distinction is between harm (in general) and benefits and consequently, between rules of non-infliction, prevention, and removal of harm on the one hand, and rules of promoting the good/producing benefits on the other. Many philosophers treat harms and benefits as comparative and symmetrical, as if they were on a scale with positive and negative numbers. Moving up the scale is to be benefitted and moving down the scale is to be harmed. However, this is at odds with the phenomenology of harms and benefits. As pointed out by Seana Shiffrin, a characteristic of enduring harm is that it creates a significant conflict between a person’s will and her experience:
Although harms differ from one another in various ways, all have in common that they render agents or a significant or close aspect of their lived experience like that of an endurer as opposed to that of an active agent, genuinely engaged with her circumstances, who selects, or endorses and identifies with, the main components of her life (Shiffrin 1999: 123).
A characteristic of “pure” benefits, i.e., benefits that do not also involve removal or prevention of harm, is that their absence does not produce the same kind of significant conflict between the person’s will and her experience. It just sounds weird to say that absence of a certain good (even a major good) is something a person has to endure or suffer. Shiffrin argues (I think convincingly) that due to this difference there is a moral asymmetry “between harm bestowed to prevent harm and harm bestowed to confer a pure benefit” (Shiffrin 1999: 128). For example, breaking a person’s arm as a necessary means to rescue him from mortal danger is clearly morally justified. In contrast, breaking his arm would not be justified (at least not clearly) in an attempt to bestow a pure benefit, even a very significant one. We can largely explain this asymmetry by another characteristic of benefits: if unsought, i.e., merely bestowed on us, benefits “are not as good as benefits that the recipient has chosen to pursue and has succeeded in obtaining” (Velleman 2008: 248). It is much more obvious that we should always accept and welcome other people’s attempts to protect us from harm than their (well-meaning) attempts to bestow benefits on us.

The implication for PBE’s division of nonmaleficence and beneficence seems to me to be this: By lumping together the prevention and removal of harm with promotion of the good under the principle of beneficence, Beauchamp and Childress concur with the problematic comparative and symmetrical view. I think this lends undue support to their denial that obligations of nonmaleficence are usually more stringent than obligations of beneficence (Beauchamp & Childress 2013: 151f). It is significant that the counterexamples they produce are about inflicting harm as a means to prevent greater harms rather than as a means to produce a benefit.2

My motivation for presenting these substantial controversies is twofold. On the one hand, they lend support to PBE’s clear distinction between beneficence and nonmaleficence, instead of understanding them as aspects of a unitary principle as in BR. On the other hand, they open up the possibility that an alternative distinction is sometimes more significant: the distinction between harms and benefits. I am thus not entirely convinced that PBE’s distinction should be the definitive one. I will return to the important asymmetry considerations when discussing “procreative beneficence” below.

From persons to autonomy

The other difference between the principles of BR and PBE is related to the first. On the face of it, “respect for persons” looks like a much broader concern than “respect for autonomy”. However, this is actually not the case in BR:

Respect for persons incorporates at least two basic ethical convictions: first, that individuals should be treated as autonomous agents, and second, that persons with diminished autonomy are entitled to protection (National Commission 1978: 4).

The second conviction is arguably covered by the principle of nonmaleficence in PBE, in which case all (both) aspects of respect for persons are well covered. Nevertheless, this is a point where approaches to bioethics based on relational ethics or ethics of care have criticized both BR and PBE. One point of critique is that we owe persons more than just respect for their autonomy, e.g., respect for and protection of their personal integrity and personal dignity (Rendtorff & Kemp 2000).

As a practical example of the relevance of such considerations, consider palliative and hospice care where these principles arguably play a central role (Nelson 2003, Ryndes & Emanuel 2003). Good hospice care aims at establishing an open and stable environment in order for the patient to retain her social integrity, e.g., in terms of meaningful time together with family and friends. The threat of physical, mental, and social disintegration experienced by many terminal patients is not only about loss of autonomy understood as self-determination and self-control, even if respect for autonomy may very well be instrumental for protecting the person’s integrity. It seems reasonable to claim that concern for integrity should sometimes be a more basic consideration than respect for autonomy.


Recognition and protection of dignity is another prevalent concern here. Ethical guidelines for hospice care invariably emphasize the importance of treating each and every dying person as irreplaceable and unique, not just a case or a task to be solved as efficiently as possible in order to make hospice beds available for more needy patients. Thus, a possible strength of an expanded principle of respect for persons is that it provides a justification for the claim that patients with diminished capacity for autonomy are still owed the same level of protection: out of concern for their integrity and in recognition of their dignity
.


The concept of human dignity may seem hopelessly vague and this has led many bioethicists to a rather defeatist attitude.3
It may be relevant to point out that the concept of autonomy is not exactly clear and distinct either, at least not absent serious philosophical analysis. There is a certain tendency in many health care systems to understand patients as units in a system of hospital productivity. This typically involves disregard for autonomy, which seems to me to be a symptom of a deeper problem, namely that such reduction is an indignity, since it treats the patient as a kind of commodity or production item and thus disregards the patient’s basic human worth.4

Beauchamp and Childress could of course argue that the principle of beneficence covers such considerations. After all, physical and social integrity, and being treated as a person rather than an item or a task is in the best interest of the patient. The main reason to be skeptical about such a proposal is analogous to the reasons to insist on respect for autonomy as an independent principle: You want to be respected as a person with values, hopes, dreams, and attachments, not just treated “beneficently” as a container of miscellaneous interests
.


Principles in reproductive ethics

So much for the discussion of PBE’s version of principlism. I now turn to the debate about procreative obligations in reproductive ethics. I mentioned at the outset that this debate is nearly absent in PBE. At first glance, it seems that PBE’s principles are nonetheless well proven in reproductive ethics. The overall reproductive ethics debate apparently maps quite neatly onto the principlist framework. There are straightforward questions to ask and distinct debates related to all four principles. More than that: There seem to be no substantial debates that center on principles presenting an alternative to PBE. In this section, I will give a brief overview of some influential contributions.


Respect for Procreative Autonomy

The expanding range of procreative choices due to biotechnology would seem to involve an enhancement of parental autonomy. What used to be results of chance and luck will increasingly become matters of choice. Whether the availability of such choices actually increases autonomy turns out to be a matter of controversy, however. To be presented with vast amounts of information about risks, chances and opportunities for interventions and manipulations may lead to an overload in which genuine autonomy may in fact be compromised. The context of choice may be biased towards certain options being the rational or responsible ones, so that the choice may not be that free after all. People grappling with such issues will find invaluable resources for analysis and qualified solutions in PBE.


The same goes for classical questions about parental autonomy versus the autonomy of the "person in prospect", e.g., the tension between parents' freedom to select for and against certain traits and capacities on the one hand and claims about the child's best interest, autonomy and "right to an open future" on the other (Feinberg 1980, Kass 2003). On closer inspection, however, it seems that the particular problem of parental choices about future people does move beyond the field covered by PBE. According to Jürgen Habermas, procreative choices potentially put future autonomy in jeopardy in two novel ways. First, an obstacle for authentic responsibility for self arises if a person's prospects, potentials, and capabilities turn out to be the result of a detailed, instrumentalist design by parents, genetic consultants or others. Second, the inbuilt inequality between generations of such an arrangement seems to enhance the autonomy of the creator-generation at the cost of the created generation (Habermas 2001). Such objections to unrestrained parental choice are nevertheless normally brought forward on the background assumption that procreative autonomy should be respected (ceteris paribus). People should be free to make their own choices about how and when to procreate, which values and goals to pursue in raising a family and so on
.

Procreative Justice

The principle of justice has perhaps been the one least utilized in reproductive ethics. Most bioethicists seem to prefer alternative principles to capture considerations about the ethically right way for prospective parents to relate to their offspring. The chapter on the principle of justice in PBE is mainly concerned with questions of fairness and entitlements concerning allocation of and access to health care resources, questions that do not relate directly to procreative choices per se. On the other hand, procreative decisions do raise obvious questions about the just distribution of risks and benefits and about equal status between generations (Habermas 2001). Some of the considerations about vulnerability and exploitation also seem to have an obvious bearing on prospective parents’ obligations to their offspring.


Jeffrey Reiman (2007: 81) has argued that intentionally bringing disabled people into being violates their right to a normal level of functioning. He argues (plausibly) that such a right would be an outcome of Rawls’ “original position” (Rawls 1971). What would be considered important in the original position are the personal and social properties of persons (their luck in the genetic and social lottery), not which particular individuals they are (which is hidden by the veil of ignorance) (Reiman 2007: 85f.). In the next section, I will come back to a recent argument about wronging future children that may be understood in terms of justice or fairness.


Procreative Beneficence

It is obvious that procreative choices involve considerations about beneficence. Most parents are strongly preoccupied with the prospective child's future well-being. We want the best for our children. According to Julian Savulescu, such considerations imply a principle of procreative beneficence. In its original formulation, it read like this:

Couples (or single reproducers) should select the child, of the possible children they could have, who is expected to have the best life, or at least as good a life as the others, based on the relevant, available information (Savulescu 2001: 415).

This is an extreme version of such a principle – it is in effect a principle of procreative perfectionism. We will see in the next section that there are a number of relevant objections to such a principle, at least as a sovereign or dominant one. Savulescu’s principle also reflects a well-known tension in the notion of beneficence: exactly whom are we supposed to benefit – individuals or collectives? Moral philosophers working within an ethics of care or relational ethics (e.g., Noddings 1995, Gilligan 1995) and utilitarians could agree that we should benefit other people. However, it makes quite a difference whether our focus is on the (concrete) other or the (generalized) others. Similarly, the Principle of Procreative Beneficence does not tell us whether we should interpret “best life” as “best for the person whose life it is” or “best for the overall state of the world.”


Savulescu’s own answer seems to depend on the circumstances. In a subsequent article, he and Kahane lean towards the individualist interpretation since the principle is now formulated in terms of the child “whose life can be expected […] to go best” (Savulescu & Kahane 2009: 274, emphasis mine). The authors make it plain that the aim should be the child who will enjoy the highest possible level of well-being. In other works, however, Savulescu’s focus is on overall benefits to society. This is the case in his defense of “moral enhancement,” where genetic selection and genetic modification should aim at creating morally better people in order to avoid social problems like xenophobia, crime, poverty and terrorism. All such problems, it is argued, could be remedied by modifications in the human genome (Persson & Savulescu 2008, 2010; for a forceful critique see Sparrow 2014). This reading turns procreative beneficence into a principle of "procreative altruism" (Douglas & Devolder 2013). According to this principle, selection need not necessarily be beneficial for the selected child (Elster 2011). Given the seriousness of the problems allegedly solved by moral and cognitive enhancement, this view also seems to weigh strongly against procreative autonomy.


Common to both interpretations is that they leave little if any room for procreative autonomy. As pointed out by Rob Sparrow, the principle of procreative beneficence seems to lead to rather totalitarian conclusions:
"Best" is not an idea which allows room for pluralism. Thus if we could identify an embryo which had the best possible genetics, it appears that all prospective parents would be obligated to implant clones of this embryo. This vision of a world of identical "perfect babies" looks disturbingly similar to that which motivated the "old eugenics" of the 1930s (Sparrow 2007, 54).

Savulescu has tried to meet this objection by formulating his principle in a watered down version. Reproducers now have merely “a significant moral reason,” and not an obligation, to select the best possible child (Savulescu & Kahane 2009: 274). This “significant moral reason” can (in principle) be superseded by other reasons including “the interests of parents or reproducers” (Savulescu 2007: 286). The cost of this modification is obviously that the all-things-considered implications of the Principle of Procreative Beneficence become rather vague.5


Procreative Nonmaleficence

A number of authors have argued that the principle of nonmaleficence would serve us better if we want procreative obligations to be more stringent and well-founded. There are entirely reasonable (even classical Millian) restrictions on reproductive autonomy based on the principle of procreative non-maleficence. What makes them reasonable is that we are more confident about the implications of the principle of non-maleficence than about the implications of the principle of beneficence. The ways we can harm people are relatively distinct and well known from an impartial perspective. The implications of the principle of beneficence, however, are far fuzzier and more open-ended. The questions concerning whether disabilities in general or certain disabilities in particular constitute a "negative difference maker" for well-being are already pretty complex. I think it is fair to say that matters get a lot more complicated when we start contemplating which positive traits would maximize an individual's well-being (Parker 2007, Barnes 2009, Lillehammer 2009). An obvious explanation why matters get more complicated is that candidate traits  for maximal well-being are strongly dependent on the background conception of well-being, e.g., hedonist, preference-based or objective (see Griffin 1986). Furthermore, we would normally have to possess substantial insight into the particular nature of the individual's situation to get a firm grasp of the implications of procreative beneficence, i.e., we would have to know quite a lot about the particular person's preferences, social circumstances, attachments, values and so on. In preconception scenarios, this is by definition beyond our grasp and therefore – to borrow a formulation by Jonathan Glover – we enter a space “where only a monster of self-confidence would come up with an easy judgment” (Glover 2006: 58).


In cases of severe disability, we seem to be on much firmer ground. We are normally not in doubt as to whether cerebral palsy or deafness are harmful conditions that we ought to remedy if we can and that it would be morally wrong to cause such harms to others. However, in procreation scenarios, these straightforward claims become dramatically harder to make due to the so-called non-identity problem (NIP). In the next section, I will explore as briefly as I can how the NIP affects the principle of procreative nonmaleficence. The purpose is not to come up with a novel solution to the NIP but to extract some possible lessons for principlism.

Non-identity and "Wrongful Disability"

That parents should not make choices that damage or disable their future child seems to be a straightforward application of the principle of nonmaleficence. If heavy smoking or drinking during pregnancy involves significant risks of future suffering for the child then such behavior is clearly morally wrong. In such cases, however, there is a personal identity of the people affected by the alternative behaviors (e.g., smoking vs. not smoking). What is involved here are identity considerations. However, procreative choices typically involve the kind of non-identity considerations introduced by Gregory Kavka (1982) and most famously developed by Derek Parfit (1984: Ch 16).