Introduction
and
Background
The existing literature on global justice reflects the
dominant attention given to what the rich countries
should do in order to alleviate poverty and suffering
among the global poor. This discussion has proceeded
at the expense of debates about potential obligations
of poor countries themselves. Some of the contributors
to the global justice debate such as Fiona Terry
(2000), William Easterly (2006) and Paul Collier
(2008), among others, have hinted at the need to
explore obligations of poor countries. In their works
they allude to something along the lines of, “part of
the solution for poverty in poor countries lies within
the poor countries themselves.” However, the
conclusions reached by each of them do not explicitly
emphasize the obligations of poor countries in global
justice. This trend risks encouraging complacency
among resource-poor countries like Uganda in the
implementation of global justice. In this paper, the
argument is not that the contents of present works on
global justice are wrong regarding obligations of rich
countries; nor is it that some of these contributors
would deny the importance of obligations of poor
countries in ensuring global justice. Rather the
argument of this paper is that the current debate
focuses on what rich countries should do while this
alone is unlikely to result in global justice.
Therefore, for practical and moral reasons, in
addition to the obligations of rich countries, the
debate needs to mainstream reflections on possible
obligations of poor countries and on what should be
done if they do not fulfill these obligations. The
trend of thinking beyond obligations of rich countries
in ensuring global justice is not unprecedented.
Recently, using South Africa as a case study Nicola
Barsdorf argued that middle-income countries have
moral obligations to help solve some of the problems
afflicting poorer countries (2012). Drawing on this
background, this paper argues for three kinds of
obligations of poor countries in ensuring global
justice: 1) Obligations of international justice
(non-aggression); 2) The obligation of effective
management of aid resources; and 3) The obligation to
exercise due diligence (decency). We will begin by
giving a brief survey of the ongoing discussion about
obligations for global justice with the intention to
show that, despite wide recognition of the importance
of poor country obligations, these obligations have
continuously failed to reach the same level of
prominence as those of rich countries.
The
Ongoing
Debate
To
begin
with, Peter Singer in two essays:
Famine,
Affluence and Morality (1972) and
The
Singer Solution to World Poverty (1999); and in
his book
One World: The Ethics of Globalization
(2000), is primarily concerned with justifying the
moral obligations of rich countries to give aid to the
global poor. Singer discusses at length
what
citizens and governments of affluent countries can
do in order to ensure global justice. At the
same time, however, he recognizes the importance of
obligations of poor countries for utility reasons yet
he does not pursue this subject at length.
On the other hand, in his 2008
World Poverty and
Human Rights Thomas Pogge portrays global
justice predominantly in terms of the negative duties
of affluent countries in ensuring global justice. He
argues that:
[…] we [the rich] share responsibility not
only for the damage authoritarian rulers [in poor
countries] can do to the interests of ‘their’
people, […] our governments have instigated violent
installation of many oppressive rulers in poor
countries [...] and have fostered a culture of
corruption […] (2008: 29).
In Pogge’s view, “it is quite possible that within a
different global order national factors [in poor
countries] that tend to undermine the fulfillment of
human rights would occur much less often or not at
all” (2005: 22). Like Singer, Pogge hints at the
obligations of poor countries, in particular the duty
of governments in poor countries to oppose the global
institutional order that is sustained by powerful
governments in the North and global organizations such
as the World Trade Organization (WTO) and the
International Monetary Fund (IMF). However, he does
not dedicate sufficient space to this subject.
David Miller is also concerned with the issue of “what
responsibilities do we have towards the global poor?
What must we do for them as a matter of justice?”
(2007: 231). As an allusion to the obligations of poor
countries, Miller cautions that human beings should be
treated “both as agents capable of taking
responsibility for the outcomes of their actions and
as vulnerable and needy creatures who may not be able
to lead decent lives without the help of others”
(2007: 237, italics in original text). By emphasizing
their agency Miller clearly says that citizens of poor
countries have the capacity to take decisions and
assume responsibility for their outcomes. This is a
clear indication that he believes that obligations of
poor countries are an important complement to those of
rich countries for the achievement of global justice.
Yet Miller does not mainstream this subject in his
work either.
Further, in the
The problem of Global Justice,
Thomas Nagel castigates the current unjust
international order, which he rightly blames on the
affluent countries. His argument is that “[t]he global
economy, within which the familiar inequalities are
now generated, requires a stable international system
of property rights and contractual obligations that
provide the conditions for international commerce”
(2005: 137). In Nagel’s view it is a duty of affluent
countries to reform the rules of international trade
to the benefit of poor countries.
Further suggestions regarding the need to explore
obligations of poor countries in global justice can be
found in the works of Terry (2000), Easterly (2006),
and Collier (2008). From her experience of how aid to
refugees in poor countries is mismanaged, Fiona Terry,
in
Condemned to Repeat? The paradox of
humanitarian action, concludes that “[i]f
international agencies [and all donors] are to meet
the needs of the populations in crisis, their [donors]
organizational behavior must adjust to the wider
political and socio-economic contexts in which aid
occurs.” Yet, from her research findings which led her
to draw this conclusion, a complementary conclusion
can also be drawn: If international agencies are to
meet the needs of populations in crisis in poor
countries, poor countries must bear a stringent
obligation not to mismanage aid resource. Hence, even
though Terry does not explicitly suggest the need for
poor countries to bear some obligations, her findings
clearly suggest this need.
Furthermore, in
The White Man’s Burden,
Easterly sets out to investigate “[w]hy the West’s
efforts to aid the rest have done so much ill and so
little good,” (2006: 115) and comes to the conclusion
that “[i]t is all about [bad] politics” in poor
countries; and this blame is shared by International
Financial Institutions (IFIs), which he accuses of
“coddling awful gangsters who just call themselves a
government” in poor countries (Easterly 2006:
152–153). His point concerns the complicity between
government bureaucrats of poor countries,
multinational corporations and IFIs. The implication
being that in order to break down the complicity
between the representatives of rich countries and
government bureaucrats of poor countries it is
important that, for example, Pogge’s argument for
negative duties on the part of rich countries be
supplemented with duties imposed on poor country
governments to desist from complicity.
Further still, even though Collier’s
The Bottom
Billion: Why are poor countries failing and what can
be done about it (2008) does not deal with
explicit obligations of poor countries, and these
obligations are not given any direct or considerable
attention, on many occasions he does allude to
something along those lines, however. For example,
while he believes that one of the challenges for
Africa’s development is bad governance which needs
external help in the form of technical assistance, he
cautions that this kind of aid can only be effective
if the political conditions in the benefiting country
are favorable (Collier 2008: 108–115). In other words,
if any kind of aid to poor countries is to be
effective, governments of poor countries have a duty
to create favorable conditions for such aid.
Generally, there is a great deal of evidence that most
contributors to the debate about global justice
recognize, in the back of their mind, the importance
of obligations of poor countries in ensuring global
justice. Yet at the same time it is also evident that
a discussion of these obligations is far less
developed than that of the obligations of rich
countries. Since, like those sampled above, most
contributors imply that obligations of poor countries
are also important for purposes of effectiveness and
yet then fail to dedicate sufficient attention to such
obligations, there is a need to bridge this gap.
Accordingly, this work should be seen as supplementary
to their contribution to the debate rather than as a
criticism of their work.
Poor
Countries’
Obligations Relating to International Justice
Obligations
of
international justice are understood here as treaty
obligations and prohibition of interventions in
legitimate internal affairs of other countries. In
principle they apply equally to both poor and rich
countries. For this reason it may be tempting to
take these obligations for granted in relation to
poor countries and negate the need for special
discussion. However, this would only ring true under
international law. As international law is quite
complex and difficult to implement, these
obligations would benefit from being integrated into
debates about global justice founded on diffuse
pressure to secure compliance. Hence, the
obligations of poor countries in international
justice need to be emphasized and made more
stringent than they currently are in discussion of
global justice — as illustrated below using the duty
of non-aggression.
The popular discussion on international justice
concentrates on demonstrating and castigating the
guilt of rich countries in international justice. As
shown above, this has been the primary concern of
key contributors to the global justice debate
(Miller 2007; Nagel 2005; Pogge 2001, 2005, 2008,
among others). Don Scheid has argued that “[a] great
part of global justice must concern itself with the
use of force, especially the aggressive use of
force. In the quest for global justice and
international governance, one strategy is to impose
legal constraints on the use of force by outlawing
acts and wars of aggression” (2003). But even for a
case as clear as the prohibition of aggression, the
popular debate about global (social) justice is
silent when it comes to obligations of poor
countries in cases of non-aggression.
1
In this section we want to show that even though
poor countries are victims of global social
injustice, they are also at times perpetrators of
injustice against other poor nations and states.
Therefore, in the pursuit of global justice, there
is a need to seriously evaluate the moral dilemma of
dealing with
harmful victims.
2
We will use Uganda as a case to illustrate this
point.
Poor
Countries,
Armed Aggression and Global Justice
In
considering
the case of armed aggression in a paper discussing
issues related to the ethics of underdevelopment,
mal-development and associated injustices, it is
important to concede that issues of social justice
are often treated separately than those of conflict
and post-conflict situations. However, a country
that engages in destructive armed aggression against
another deprives its victim of material livelihoods
and socially afflicts its citizens, thus affecting
their material and social well-being, which are key
indicators on their Human Development Index (HDI).
The comparison of inter-country HDI is the most
important criterion in assessing the status of
global justice. Hence, if the focus of debates about
social justice is the analysis and assessment of the
causes and solutions of global inequalities in
material and social well-being, then all relevant
factors that directly affect economic and social
well-being ought to be accounted for and examined.
One major factor in this category is armed
aggression.
The
Uganda-Democratic
Republic of Congo Case
Between
1997
and 2003, the Ugandan army (Uganda People’s Defense
Forces – UPDF), invaded the Democratic Republic of
the Congo (DRC), ostensibly to fight the Allied
Democratic Forces (ADF) who were rebelling against
the Ugandan government. However, contrary to their
proclaimed justification, the army looted minerals,
timber and other resources, destroyed the
livelihoods of local citizens, conscripted children
into the army, and committed other inhumane crimes
such as rape. Other offenses also included
facilitating rebel activities in the regions they
invaded (International Court of Justice (ICJ) 2005).
According to the findings of the ICJ, “THE COURT,”
by sixteen votes to one,
Finds that the Republic of Uganda, by
engaging in military activities against the
Democratic Republic of the Congo on the latter’s
territory, by occupying Ituri and by actively
extending military, logistic, economic and
financial support to irregular forces having
operated on the territory of the DRC, violated the
principle of non-use of force in international
relations and the principle of non-intervention
(ICJ 2005: 280).
Further, by the same vote (16:1) it was agreed that:
The Republic of Uganda, by the conduct
of its armed forces, which committed acts of
killing, torture and other forms of inhumane
treatment of the Congolese civilian population,
destroyed villages and civilian buildings […]
violated its obligations under international human
rights law and international humanitarian law (ICJ
2005: 280).
In addition, the International Court of Justice
found that:
[…] the Republic of Uganda, by acts of
looting, plundering and exploitation of Congolese
natural resources committed by members of the
Ugandan armed forces in the territory of the
Democratic Republic of the Congo and by its
failure to comply with its obligations as an
occupying power in Ituri district to prevent acts
of looting, plundering and exploitation of
Congolese natural resources, violated obligations
owed to the Democratic Republic of the Congo under
international law (ICJ 2005: 280-281).
Uganda was found guilty of so many counts of
injustice that they cannot all be listed here.
Ultimately, the International Court of Justice in
the vote of sixteen to one unanimously, “[f]inds
that the Republic of Uganda is under obligation to
make reparation to the Democratic Republic of the
Congo for the injury caused; [...]” (ICJ 2005: 281).
The reparation was set at $10 billion USD; this
implies that as a result of the invasion by Uganda,
DRC loss of property, life, and well-being was
valued at $10 billion USD. While of course this
seems to be an issue which can be addressed purely
by International Law, it is important to show how
incorporating this subject in discussions about
global justice would be instrumental in efforts
towards achieving global justice.
As mentioned above, the issue of armed aggression
becomes of interest in the debate about global
justice due to its direct effect on material and
non-material well-being of the victims. Since this
issue was left purely to the realm of international
law it may have been considered a settled question,
yet no justice has been achieved thus far as long as
Uganda lacks the capacity, or is unwilling, to pay
the reparation. However, if this had been stated in
advance as a stringent obligation of social justice
upon Uganda, social pressure exerted through
diplomacy would very likely have, to a large extent,
played a preventive role in the first place.
Therefore, regarding the characterization of the
specific obligations of poor countries in ensuring
global justice, it can be said that since the level
of material and non-material well-being are key
proxies for global justice, it is important that
poor countries’ obligation to desist from armed
aggression against other nations and states should
be made more stringent because such aggression
directly tilts the balance of global justice against
victims. Of course this obligation is borne by the
rich countries too, but the point here is that since
there is evidence that through the violation of this
obligation some poor countries have exacerbated the
material and social well-being of others, hence in
the discussion of the obligations of poor countries
this obligation warrants special emphasis.
The implication of the above case is that failure to
fulfill obligations of international justice (for
example of non-aggression) and the consequent damage
leads to injustice against those who must repair the
damage through relief and development aid. For
example, since Uganda could not alleviate the
deprivation in the DRC as it lacked the requisite
resource capacity to do that, then, following David
Miller’s criteria for assigning remedial
responsibility in global justice (2007), the natural
place to look is the agent with the capacity to
alleviate the harm – the governments and citizens of
affluent countries. However, if the citizens of
affluent countries are subjected to enforceable
obligations to provide aid for alleviating harm
inflicted by other countries in this way, it
constitutes a clear injustice, especially if no
sanctions are meted out against perpetrators for
flouting their obligations. It is for this reason
that when thinking about global justice, poor
countries must bear the positive as well as negative
obligations of international justice. If poor
countries fail on these counts then they ought to
suffer the sanctions attached to corresponding
obligations.
However, in dealing with harmful victims like
Uganda, sanctions imposed for failure on their
obligations are likely to engender moral dilemmas.
It raises other issues pertaining to the relations
between the citizens of poor countries and their
governments. Ordinarily, when one speaks of the
duties and responsibilities of poor countries, these
should be duties and responsibilities of the
governments and the citizens jointly. However, this
would only be the case if governments of poor
countries were as representative as those of the
democratic and affluent countries, such that the
actions and inactions of governments are influenced,
and therefore owned by their citizens. This dilemma
does not only arise in the implementation of
international justice obligations, but also in many
other instances. We will return to this and other
challenges towards the conclusion.
Obligation
Pertaining
to Aid
In
discussing
strategies for global justice, obligation to aid is
dominant. However, aid can be a double-edged sword
for and against poor countries. Whereas aid can
provide immediate relief to the global poor, it can
also be abused by aid-givers to create an
exploitative dependency relationship between the
poor and the rich and in this way uphold global
injustices. However each of these two possibilities
depends on how aid is conceived. If aid is conceived
as charity, it can easily be abused to uphold global
injustices. But on the other hand if it is
understood as a right of needy people worldwide and
is organized in the form of, for example, Pogge’s
concept of the Global Resource Dividend (GRD) (Pogge
2008), then it would be very difficult to abuse. In
this paper, aid is understood in the latter sense.
Besides, giving aid is just one of the duties and
obligations of rich countries and these other duties
and obligations should forestall the misuse of aid
by its givers in this way.
Whereas generally the economics of “Trade not Aid”
is based on valid arguments in relation to the
sustainability of development of poor countries, aid
may still be an inevitable obligation in global
justice. In order to understand the inevitability of
aid in efforts to achieve global justice, Miller’s
point about vulnerability mentioned above needs to
be taken seriously. This is because it is a
self-evident truth that even if all countries
observed requirements of international justice, fair
trade regimes and so forth, many people around the
world would still remain below the material and
social threshold needed for ensuring the level of
well-being that is considered just. Local conditions
– natural and those amenable to human efforts,
market failures, technical and technological
deficits etc. – would still render citizens of some
countries socially and economically vulnerable,
especially those in low-income countries. This fact
leads to a moral requirement on those who have
surplus resources to transfer some of these to those
who are in need. To emphasize the importance of aid
in global justice David Miller emphasizes that in
order to determine the extent of global liabilities
on nations and states, “we need the idea of a global
minimum – a set of basic human rights which must be
protected for people everywhere regardless of
circumstances” (2007: 266). Charles Jones too
defends basic human rights as the “moral minimum”
required for the implementation of global justice
(1999: 50–84). All these imply the stringency of the
obligation to give aid as a matter of right of the
poor.
Conversely, however, Terry (2000), Easterly (2006),
Collier (2008) and many others have been concerned
with the effectiveness of aid in poor countries and
are all highly skeptical. Their analyses indicate
that, for aid to be effective, certain conditions
must exist within poor countries; or to put it
differently, for such aid to be effective,
governments of poor countries ought to bear and
fulfill some relevant obligations. This point serves
to re-emphasizes the main point of this paper; that
is, the obligations of poor countries and
discussions about them are important supplements to
those of rich countries if the mission of global
justice is to be achieved and be achieved justly.
Hence, drawing on evidence-based skepticism about
the effectiveness of aid in poor countries, the
point of this argument is that when governments of
poor countries receive aid they incur obligations
pertaining to the effectiveness with which such aid
is managed; and that failure to meet such
obligations ought to attract all sanctions available
against governments. But there also lingers a
question regarding whether or not rich countries
should withhold aid to poor countries should the
governments of the latter fail to fulfill their
obligations. We will come back to this question
later.
Obligation
of
Effective Management of Aid
In
conceiving
the obligations of poor countries, one of the
relevant (hypothetical) questions to ask is: “What
if the aid they receive from affluent countries as a
result of rich countries fulfilling their obligation
to aid, never trickles down to its intended
beneficiaries or is never converted into the desired
well-being for ordinary citizens?” The implication
here is that governments of poor countries are
representatives or
agents3
of their citizens who bear an obligation to deliver
aid to the citizens who are the intended
beneficiaries as effectively as possible. In other
words, the right to aid resides in the citizens not
their agents (governments). This implies that even
if governments of poor countries fail when it comes
to this obligation, this does not exempt the
affluent countries from giving aid to those they owe
it to – the ordinary poor citizens in poor
countries. Instead, the failure of poor country
governments to fulfill this obligation adds another
duty to aid-givers: that is, to find other feasible
channels through which to fulfill their obligations.
The obligation to effectively manage aid is
important for both practical and moral reasons. From
a practical point of view, this is necessary as a
complement to that of rich countries giving aid. In
other words, for aid to make any impact on the lives
of the poor, the governments concerned must be able
and willing to convert it into desired well-being.
From a moral point of view, if governments of poor
countries behave as economic ‘black holes’ by way of
mismanaging aid resources, then this will impose an
unjust magnitude of burden on those who bear the
obligation to give aid. (This point will be given
more emphasis in arguing for the next obligation
below.) It is these two reasons that would justify
sanctions against poor country governments that fail
to meet this obligation.
But, again here, there is a lurking dilemma involved
in imposing obligations on poor countries,
particularly sanctions in the case of failure to
meet their obligations. For example, Pogge raises
the issue of autocracy in poor countries and
complicity of the elite therein with representatives
of affluent nations harming the interests of the
citizens in poor countries. In other words, Pogge
would rightly argue that “the poor countries that
perpetrate harms such as aggression or may fail on
any obligations are not the same as the poor
countries that are the intended beneficiaries of
global justice”. The former refers to the
governments (the elite and bureaucrats), while the
latter are the ordinary citizens, and these two
should not be treated as one entity in the
conception and implementation of obligations of poor
countries. This means that it would be an injustice
for the citizens of poor countries to be made to
suffer any sanctions arising from their governments’
failure to fulfill their obligations. Therefore, in
thinking about poor countries’ obligations for
international justice, the primary focus ought to be
the governments of poor countries. This means that
if there are any sanctions to be imposed on poor
countries for failure to fulfill their obligations
then care must be taken to limit the effects of such
sanctions to governments and not the poor citizens.
Contributory
Negligence
and the Duty of Due Diligence
The
Principle
of Contributory Negligence
Contributory
or
comparative negligence is a juridical principle. It
means carelessness or lack of vigilance on the part
of the plaintiff which (carelessness) has
contributed to, and is in whole or in part the cause
of the injury or harm he [or she] complains of, as
having been caused to him [or her] by the
defendant’s fault. Contributory negligence is one’s
failure to avoid getting hurt by the defendant or it
is the fault of the claimant in the very occurrence
of the accident (GLH 1982: 587). The principle
implies that failure by a person to exercise
reasonable care for the safety of either himself [or
herself] or his [or her] property so that he [or
she] becomes blameworthy in part or in whole as an
author of his [or her] own harm does not impose
liability on the defendant. Therefore, under the
principle of contributory negligence, justice
demands that before the potential obligation bearer
(defendant) is assigned the duty to compensate the
victim, it should be inquired into to establish
whether there was anything the victim of harm could
have been reasonably expected to do in order to
avoid harm suffered or mitigate its severity. On
this account, the potential victims of injustice are
believed to have a duty to exercise due diligence or
reasonable care in order to avoid or mitigate harm
to themselves. The implication of this principle is
that it would be an injustice to assign a hundred
percent obligation to rectify the harm to the
obligation bearer (defendant), although part of the
harm can be attributed to the negligence of the
victim.
The principle of contributory negligence, sometimes
called comparative negligence, arises in debates
about global justice out of the following
hypothetical question: “Is there anything poor
countries can do or avoid in their governance to
reduce their suffering so that they require less or
no aid at all?” If this question is answered in the
affirmative, then there should be an obligation of
poor countries to exercise
reasonable care4 or due diligence; that
is, given evidence of rampant contributory
negligence in poor countries, the specific
obligations of poor countries arising from the
question posed above would be that governments in
poor countries have a duty and obligation to ensure
due diligence in managing the economies of these
countries. The relevance of this obligation or duty
in relation to poor countries is based on the
assumption (to be proved below) that governments of
poor countries display what would constitute
avoidable negligence or recklessness in the
management of their affairs.
It is important to note that a discussion of this
principle and its arising duty takes into account
the fact that factors that cause and worsen global
injustice are both local and international or global
in nature; these being both natural and those
amenable to human efforts. Hence, the argument being
advanced here is that irrespective of whether the
causes of global injustice are local or
international; natural or purely dependent of human
efforts, the exercise of reasonable care by the poor
countries in the management of their affairs can
facilitate efforts to mitigate them, eventually
leading to global justice.
Extrapolating
the
Principle into Global Justice Debate
Charles
Jones
accepts that the rich should have an enforceable
obligation in implementing social justice. However,
he argues that “[i]n addition, avoidable activities
which make it less likely that poor countries can
meet their own citizens rights-claims could be
disallowed, thus enabling those states to fulfill
their obligations with less positive aid from other
states” (1999: 70). By arguing that certain
activities be disallowed in developing countries,
Jones implies that in poor countries there are
activities which can be regarded as reckless or not
prudent enough to the extent that they stand in the
way of ensuring that their citizens enjoy material
and social conditions comparable to those which
global justice intends to achieve for them. But in
addition to Jones’ negative requirement of
refraining from harmful activities, poor countries
can also be required to take certain prudent
positive steps (activities) with diligence,
incumbent in their obligations in ensuring global
justice. Both these positive and negative steps
should be those that, if taken, would forestall most
of the causes of global injustice, whether these be
domestic or international; artificial or natural.
This argument implies that governments who flout
these obligations would henceforth be liable to
corresponding sanctions. Therefore, the principle of
contributory or comparative negligence and its
arising duty of exercising due diligence can be
legitimately extrapolated into the debates of global
justice.
Should
Poor
Countries Bear Duties of Due Diligence?
Looking
at
the argument raised by Jones above through the lens
of the principle of contributory negligence, the
answer to the question above depends on whether
there is evidence that governments in poor countries
are not diligent (decent) enough by way of what
might be called recklessness in their governance
systems. Should this issue prove to be the case,
then at least two negative outcomes would arise: the
first one is that, even if obligations of rich
countries are met, they would not achieve global
justice; secondly, it would be an injustice to
coerce citizens of the rich countries to transfer
resources to governments of poor countries in what
may seem like rewarding recklessness. In light of
the above question, the quality of governance in
poor countries seems to point directly to the need
to emphasize their duty to ensure due diligence.
To begin with, O’Neill raises the issue of
population explosion in poor countries and argues
that this worsens their already dire situation
(O’Neill 1986: 158). O’Neill’s claim is corroborated
by population growth statistics in poor countries,
which show that globally the highest population
growth rates are recorded in poor countries. For
example, according to population growth statistics
for 2011, Uganda has the fifth highest population
growth rate globally at 3.2 % per annum, after the
United Arab Emirates (UAE) (4.9 %); Bahrain (4.8 %);
Zambia (4.2 %) and Niger (3.5 %) (World Bank 2013).
Elsewhere, Uganda is ranked third globally with an
annual population growth rate of 3.576 % after
Zimbabwe (4.31 %) and Niger (3.643 %). Generally,
African countries which are most burdened by poverty
and disease top population growth rate rankings
(NationMaster 2013). O’Neill’s argument is based on
the assumption that population explosion has a
negative impact on the socio-economic well-being of
people (in terms of income, savings, health etc.).
If this assumption is correct then in order to
improve socio-economic conditions in poor countries
(such as household savings and health conditions)
poor countries should bear the obligation of
reducing their population growth rates.
However, the argument about population control as
presented by O’Neill above can arguably suffer from
two potential doubts: One is that it appears to put
the cart before the horse. This is because in some
cases population growth seems to be dependent on
economic and social development and therefore very
difficult to control in itself; that is, low
birth-rates being regarded as a consequence of
improved socio-economic conditions especially health
care and education. However, at the same time it is
possible that low population growth rates are a
precondition for improvement in standards of living.
It is plausible to argue that a poor country that
prioritizes population control in its resource
allocation and public policy will quickly reduce
both government and household expenditures and at
the same time reduce pressure on the limited social
services. The second potential problem may arise
from the legitimacy of authoritarian and corrupt
governments in poor countries to enforce population
control. But since such enforcement would be in the
best interest of the citizens, then this could be
allowed for and count as at least one credit to such
governments.
Further, some of the practices in poor countries,
especially those pertaining to governance, justify
the imposition of the duty to exercise due
diligence. Drawing from the general criticism
against aid raised by Terry, Easterly and Collier
among others as pointed out above, the factors which
undermine the effectiveness of aid can be
exemplified in specific countries. These factors
count as failure to exercise due diligence among
poor countries. For example, Uganda which relies
heavily on the Global Fund and other external aid
sources for the health sector has several times been
implicated in what can count as negligence. This is
evidenced by very high levels of corruption with
impunity. In this case, high levels of corruption
with impunity constitutes clear failure of the
principle of due diligence on the part of
government. There are some particular popular cases
that confirm this failure: In 2007 it was discovered
that “[a]s thousands of Ugandans die every day of
HIV/Aids and malaria, drugs worth about UGX 4
billion [around $1.6 million USD] are rotting [have
expired] in the National Medical Stores Entebbe”
(Nandutu 2007). It was also revealed that “[s]tolen
government drugs [are] repackaged and resold to
National Medical Stores” (Ayebazibwe 2012). Other
poor countries have been found guilty too and they
have also been either asked to refund the Global
Fund money or forfeit subsequent rounds of funding.
These include Pakistan, Ukraine, Myanmar, Senegal,
Chad, Nigeria, Kenya, Zimbabwe, Namibia, and Togo,
to mention but a few (IRIN 2009).
To further illustrate the point, one can look at a
sample of Uganda’s “Nine Corruption Scandals to Look
Back at” (New Vision, 2014). According to this
research, in only nine corruption cases, at least
$0.42 billion USD was lost in the hands of different
public officials; the majority of these were
politically exempt from liability resulting in no
hope of recovering the money. Generally, according
to the results of the Corruption Perception Index
(CPI) for countries over the years, there is a high
correlation between being a corrupt country and
being a poor country. Even if it is arguable whether
corruption at a national level is a cause or an
effect of poverty, it seems to make better sense to
argue that corruption is an obstacle to social,
economic and political development and it takes
political will to successfully fight corruption.
In light of these and potentially more pieces of
evidence, the principle of contributory negligence
points to the need for poor countries to bear a
moral obligation to exercise due diligence in
managing their affairs. The pragmatic value of this
obligation is that it would make concerned
obligation bearers more vigilant and prudent in
managing their affairs. This will in turn reduce
their chances of being harmed by other agents’
behaviors or natural factors. Furthermore, from a
moral point of view it would be an injustice to ask
other obligation bearers, particularly citizens of
rich countries, to incur costs which are a result of
avoidable omissions and commissions on the part of
governments of poor countries, if there are no
efforts to hold perpetrators accountable. By and
large, ignoring the principle of contributory
negligence and its arising duty to exercise due
diligence in global justice debate would lead to
complacence, and more recklessness on the part of
the governments of poor countries, making it more
difficult to achieve global injustice. Therefore,
poor countries ought to bear an obligation/duty to
exercise due diligence in order to mitigate the
level of injustice they suffer and also reduce the
liability of other agents.
Some
Potentially
Persistent Challenges
The
question
of obligations of poor countries in global justice
is quite complex and this paper does not claim to
provide an exhaustive and uncontroversial account of
them. But certainly from the above discussion it has
transpired that there is a need to mainstream a
discussion of these obligations into debates about
obligations of global justice. In this effort,
however, challenges lurk that need critical
attention. Most of the challenges will potentially
arise in the implementation of these obligations.
One of these is how to hold governments of poor
countries accountable should they flout these
obligations, without harming the interests of their
needy citizens. We have treated governments and
citizens of poor countries as two different entities
as most of these governments lack legitimacy in the
sense of not being truly representative of the
interests of their citizens. Hence, since
obligations of poor countries need to be enforceable
in order to be effective, the mode of their
enforcement ought to draw a clear line between the
obligation bearer (governments) and the intended
beneficiaries of global justice. This in turn
implies that even if poor country governments flout
their obligations, rich countries retain their
obligations to the citizens of poor countries.
From the above, another challenge in the conception
and enforcement of obligations of poor countries
arises in the case of their governments failing to
fulfill their obligations: that is, how can the rich
countries fulfill their obligations to the global
poor without doing so through the agency of their
governments? Could this be done through Civil
Society Organizations (CSOs)? However, whereas the
community of civil society would promise an
effective channel, the successful operation of civil
society in any country still to a great extent
depends on the smooth relations between the two. But
since some CSOs (such as the UN and Red Cross) have
immunity against government interference, it would
be possible to bypass potential sabotage from
uncooperative governments.
One may well wonder: How can one assign obligations
to countries like Uganda that do not fulfill any, or
at least most, of the requirements of good
governance? Would it not be a waste of time? Yes, it
may appear so, especially if there are no means to
enforce such obligations internationally. But since
obligations of justice are (here) meant to be
enforceable and all obligations of poor countries
argued for above point to the requirements of good
governance, assigning governments of poor countries
related obligations seems not to be in vain.
Finally, from our arguments above, the ordinary
citizens of poor countries seem to be completely
exempt from bearing any obligations. This exemption
is also potentially controversial. From the point of
view of the importance of human agency, it can be
interpreted as an assault on the autonomy of
citizens in poor countries. It is therefore a
worthwhile exercise to consider the possibility of
such obligations (for citizens). These obligations
might relate, for example, to their vigilance and
support for the civil society and their compliance
with the positive and negative prescriptions to them
relating to actions that are aimed at improving
their conditions, hence making it easier for them to
approach the material threshold which global justice
aims at. But since the performance of individual
citizens depends on the effectiveness of public
institutions, it is proper to prioritize a
discussion of obligations of their governments. All
these issues (and probably more) are unsettled
questions in the conception and implementation of
obligations of poor countries in ensuring global
justice; however, they cannot be sufficiently
adjudicated in the limited space of this paper.
Accordingly these challenges need to be born in mind
in the discussions of obligations of poor countries
in global justice.
Conclusion
The
obligations
of poor countries are crucial for the achievement of
global justice, yet these obligations are largely
side-stepped in current discussion. At best, as is
the case with many authors, these obligations are
simply alluded to and this can reduce their
stringency. In the first place, by engaging in
aggression against other states, poor countries
deprive their victims’ material livelihoods and
social well-being – both of which have serious
ramifications on a global justice scale. Secondly,
although not the most important condition for the
development of poor countries, obligation to aid is
crucial in global justice, yet experience shows that
its effectiveness is not guaranteed due to moral
weaknesses in poor country governments. For this
reason, when governments of poor countries receive
aid, they ought to incur stringent obligations to
effectively manage such resources to the benefit of
its intended beneficiaries. Thirdly, given the
available evidence about the poor quality of
governance in most poor countries it has been shown
that poor countries are morally liable to bear the
duty of exercising due diligence in the management
of their affairs. Finally, it is important to
emphasize the point that, the discussion in this
paper does not constitute a denial of the importance
of the obligations of rich countries; rather it is
an emphasis of the additional obligations of the
governments of poor countries. If we emphasize the
obligations of the governments of rich countries and
neglect those of poor countries, it will not be
possible for the citizens in poor countries to
benefit from the efforts of rich countries and it
will engender injustice against citizens of affluent
countries.
Notes
1 Rich countries too,
may, or actually do, engage in armed aggression, but
the concern of this paper is the obligations of poor
countries.
2 By harmful victims, we
mean victims of global injustice (poor countries),
but whose domestic and international behavior is
harmful to their citizens and other countries, as we
illustrate using the case of Uganda. This creates a
dilemma as to whether such harmful victims deserve
positive actions such as aid from the affluent
countries.
3 By saying that
governments of poor countries act as agents of their
citizens, we are not committed to saying that such
governments are representative in a truly democratic
sense. Rather, we mean that whatever such
governments receive or do is all purportedly done in
the name of their citizens.
4 According to Gerald N.
Hill and Kathleen T. Hill (1981–2005), ‘Reasonable
Care’ refers to the degree of caution and concern
for the safety of oneself and others that an
ordinarily prudent and rational person would apply
in the circumstances.
Literature
Armed
Activities on the Territory of the Congo (Democratic
Republic of the Congo V. Uganda), Judgment, I.C.J.
Reports 2005, p. 168.
Ayebazibwe,
A.
(2012) Stolen government drugs repackaged and resold
to National Medical Stores, The
Daily Monitor, 3rd Nov.
Barsdorf,
N.
W. (2012) South
Africa’s
Duty to Support Health Research for the Global
Poor. PhD
diss., University of Bergen, Norway.
Choudhari
Fuljibhai
v. Fakirmohaned [1982] GLH 578. Contributory and
Composite Negligence.
Collier,
P. (2008) The
Bottom
Billion: Why are poor countries failing and what
can be done about it. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Easterly,
W.
(2006) The
white man’s burden: Why the West’s efforts to aid
the rest have done so much ill and so little good.
New York: The Penguin Press.
Golding,
M. P. (1975) Philosophy
of
Law. Englewood: Cliffs, New Jersey:
Prentice-Hall.
Hart, H.
L. A. (1979) Between Utility and Rights. In: The Idea
of freedom, ed. R.
Alan, pp. 828–846. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hill, G.
& Hill, K. (1981–2005). Legal Dictionary.
Retrieved fromdictionary.law.com/Default.aspx?review=true
IRIN
(2009) Global: Falling foul of the fund. Retrieved
fromwww.irinnews.org/Report81295/GLOBAL-Falling-foul-of-the-Fund
Jones,
C. (1999) Global
Justice:
Defending cosmopolitanism. Oxford:
Oxford
University Press.
Nagel,
T.
(2005) The Problem of Global Justice. Philosophy
and Public Affairs,33, (2), pp. 113–147.
Nandutu,
A. (2007) Shs3.7 Billion Malaria, ARV Drugs Rot in
National Medical Stores. The
New Vision, 7th Jul.
NationMaster
(2013)
People Statistics > Population growth rate (most
recent) by country. Retrieved from www.nationmaster.com/graph
/peo_pop_pro_rat-people-population-growth-rate
Nine
corruption scandals to look back at (2012). New
Vision: Uganda’s Leading Daily, 5th Aug. www.newvision.co.ug/news/637209-
nine-corruption-scandals-to-look-back-at.html
O’Neill,
O. (1986) Faces
of Hunger: An essay on Poverty, Justice andDevelopment. London:
Allen and Unwin.
O’Neill,
O. (1996) Towards
Justice
and Virtue: A Constructive Account ofPractical
Reasoning. London:
Cambridge
University Press.
Pogge,
T. (2001) Priorities of Global Justice. In: Global Justice, ed. T.
Pogge, pp. 6–24. Oxford: Blackwell.
Pogge,
T. (2005) Human Rights and Human Responsibilities.
In: Global
Responsibilities, ed. A. Kuper, A., pp. 3–36.
New York and London: Routledge.
Pogge,
T. (2008) World
Poverty
and Human Rights (2nd Ed.).
Malden, USA: Polity Press.
Scheid,
D. E. (2012) Aggression: Humanities, Social Sciences
and Law: The Encyclopedia of Global Justice.
Retrieved fromwww.springerreference.com/docs/html/chapterdbid
/328 008.html
Shue, H.
(1996) Basic
Rights:
Subsistence, Affluence and U.S. Foreign Policy.Princeton
NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Shue, H.
(2006) Basic Rights. In: Contemporary
Political
Philosophy: An Anthology (2nd Ed.),
ed.
R. E. Goodin & P. Pettit, pp. 302–316. Australia:
Blackwell Publishing.
Singer,
P. (2000) One
World:
The Ethics of Globalization. New
Haven,
CT: Yale University Press.
Terry,
F. (2000) Condemned
to
Repeat? The paradox of humanitarian action.Cornell
Press, New York.
The
World Bank Group (2013) Democratic Republic of
Congo. fromwww.worldbank.org/en/country/drc
The
World Bank (2013) Population Growth (annual %).
Retrieved fromdata.worldbank.org/indicator/SP.POP.GROW